As discussed in the last post, the existence of the hackberry tree in my front yard, a contingent and conditional thing, ultimately depends upon the existence of an unconditioned and non-contingent thing. I also described how in like manner I can describe a chain of conditions for any contingent and conditional thing – a rock, a dog, a cow, an automobile, a person, etc. In each of these instances, we can arrive at a chain of conditions upon which its existence depends and that ends in a fundamental condition that is itself not contingent and not conditional.
So there cannot exist only contingent and conditional things in reality. Reality must also include at least one unconditioned and noncontigent thing.
What can we say about such unconditioned and noncontingent thing(s)?
First, we can say that it must be incapable of not existing. If it were capable of not existing, then it would be conditional and contingent. But as we have shown it is unconditional and noncontingent. Therefore, it cannot be capable of not existing.
Something that is not capable of not existing is termed “necessary being”. Necessary being then must be self-existent and self-sufficient.
Furthermore, there cannot be a time when necessary being did not exist. For if such necessary being had a moment when it began to exist, that would mean that its existence came from something outside itself. This would mean that it was contingent and conditional – depending on this outside thing for its own existence – and thus, would not be necessary being.
Likewise, there cannot be a time when necessary being ceases to exist. For if it was possible for it to not exist, it would be contingent and conditional and would no longer be necessary being.
In short, necessary being must have no beginning and no end.
So the real question becomes what is “necessary being”?
Modern materialism may answer that although individual things are contingent, the whole vast collection of such things taken in its entirety could be regarded as necessary. In other words, it is true that beings we experience all around us are contingent – animals, plants, rocks, humans, etc. But the universe as a whole can be regarded as necessary. That while the individual components and things contained within the vast universe are contingent, the universe is not. After all it is a scientific law that matter-energy cannot be created or destroyed. So is this matter-energy, the substratum common to all the existing things we observe in the universe, the necessary being we are searching for?
The answer, quite simply, is “no” for two reasons.
First, no collection or series of contingent beings, even if the series was infinite as regards time or space, could ever constitute a necessary being. If each member of the whole is contingent, then the whole, no matter its size or scope, does not contain within itself any sufficient reason for its existence – it simply cannot be self-existent.
Contingency is an attribute belonging to the essential nature of the object of which it is affirmed. Such attributes are predicable not merely of individuals but of the whole collection.
Likewise, the supposition that matter is the necessary being can be shown to be impossible. Matter is capable of receiving perfections that are not among its essential attributes. Matter can become a man, or gold, or a flower, etc. Each of these substances (man, gold, flower) has distinctive properties. But each of these properties is not essential to matter – for what is essential cannot be separated from it. So where do these properties come from?
Since they are not essential to matter, they must arise from the operation of some cause external to the matter.
This leads us to a principle of prime importance, i.e., whenever two things essentially distinct one from the other are found in union, this must be due to the operation of an efficient cause outside and other than the things themselves.
If two things essentially distinct, A and B, are found united or combined the reason cannot be found in A. “A” is the sufficient reason only for itself and its own essential attributes. Likewise it cannot be found in B.
For example, think of a triangle. No cause is needed to explain why a triangle should have three angles. The attribute of having three angles results immediately from the essence of a triangle as a plane figure bounded by three straight lines. You simply cannot have a triangle without three angles.
Now think of a wooden triangle. A wooden triangle is a composite reality. Wood is not triangular necessarily. Nor is a triangle necessarily wooden. The composition of these diverse elements, of necessity, supposes the operation of an efficient cause other than and outside the wood and triangle.
Necessary being is self-sufficient and self-existent. No agent can exist capable of conferring perfections upon necessary being. For this to be so, the agent must be other than and outside the necessary being. But such being other than and outside necessary being can only be contingent being. But contingent being owes whatever attributes it possesses in last resort to necessary being. Contingent being has nothing that is not already found in necessary being and cannot add anything to it. It follows then that matter which is a recipient for perfections cannot be necessary being.
Thus, necessary being cannot be a composite but rather, necessary being is absolutely simple. Also as we have shown, necessary being is not matter. Necessary being must then be immaterial.
“But”, it may be argued by some, “what if there are a plurality of necessary beings?” “Wouldn’t that invalidate the argument you just stated?”
A plurality of necessary beings is nonsensical .
Let’s suppose there are two necessary beings, A and B.
To be separate means they must in some way be distinct one from another.
To be distinct means that A must have attributes not found in the B.
But such attributes that provide this distinction are not essential to A – for if they were essential to the necessary being of A than they must, by definition, be found in the other necessary being B - which of course would dissolve any distinction.
Furthermore if the attributes are not essential to A, they must arise from a cause other than and outside A. But if A is necessary being than it is self-existent and self-sufficient– meaning that no agent can exist capable of conferring perfections upon it.
Thus the very nature of necessary being means that it can only be one.
Equally invalid is the pantheist contention (common to many Eastern religions as well as the New Age movement in the West) that contingent beings are merely modes of the one and all-inclusive Absolute - that they are manifestations of necessary being, and not entities possessed of a distinct though dependent existence. Here we may make appeal to the argument which we have just employed in regard of material substances. The contingent beings of experience are constantly undergoing changes and acquiring new perfections. This alone establishes that they are not modes of necessary being. A sheer contradiction is involved in the supposition that an agent exists, which can confer perfections on necessary being. Yet the acquisition of a perfection apart from an agent is, as we have seen, a metaphysical impossibility.
Thus we have shown in this and the previous post that there exists necessary being – that is non-conditional and non-contingent.
And that there is only one necessary being.
That this necessary being is absolutely simple, that is not a composite.
That this necessary being is immaterial.
And that this necessary being has no beginning and no end, that is eternal.
In the next post I will show two things:
1. The one, eternal, absolutely simple necessary being must be unrestricted in its power or act.
2. The one, eternal, absolutely simple necessary being is the continuous creator of all else that is.
A Return to Reason and Sanity
The rational truth of God, the immortality of the soul, and the natural law as the foundation of ethics and morality presented as the antidote to the irrationality of the "new atheism", moral relativism, and cultural subjectivsim of our age. Your civil, courteous, and thoughtful comments and ideas are welcome. This blog is a forum to discuss ideas not personalities. Thank you.
Monday, October 10, 2011
Saturday, October 8, 2011
God, Aquinas, and Dawkins: A Chain of Reason
In any quest for truth, we must firmly root ourselves in the reality of the universe in which we find ourselves. The question is how can we ensure that we are truly rooted in reality?
First, we must recognize that reality is very complicated and we must accept that we are prone to error. We must be careful not to require things to fall into neat, tidy, and easy little answers. Thinking is hard work and there are no short cuts to truth. And in our thinking, observing, and reasoning we must be consistent with the reality that is in front of us. If I start out my reasoning by denying part or all of reality, I will never reach the truth. All our knowledge, proper and improper, and all our beliefs need to be evaluated against reality. Otherwise, we are on only so many flights of fantasy whose destination is the land of unknowing – a land where each individual can determine his or her own truth, his or her own value system, and where each such truth and value system is equal to every other. (Hmmm … why does this sound so very familiar?)
Second as a means to control error, we must ground any proposition we hold in sufficient evidence to rationally prove its truth. Basically, we have three ways to do such:
1. A proposition can be affirmed by rigorous public substantiation through an agreed upon criterion which is sufficient to make a preponderance of reasonable and responsible people believe that a proposition is reasonably true – for example in science such corroboration is achieved through the repetition of experiment.
OR
2. We can show that the denial of my proposition leads to an intrinsic contradiction or impossible state of affairs.
OR
3. We can show that the denial of the proposition leads to a contradiction of publicly confirmed fact.
Only one of these is necessary to prove the truth and reasonableness of a proposition.
Third, we must be careful to clearly define terms used in our arguments and propositions. Terms should be defined so that the definitions allow for public corroboration, demonstrate non-contradiction, or demonstrate that a hypothetical proposition does not contradict a rigorously confirmed fact. The definitions of terms do not need to be all encompassing of all conditions, but the definitions do need to have sufficient meaning to successfully complete demonstration or corroboration.
Contingent and Conditional
As laid out in my previous posts, empirical science cannot prove or disprove the existence of God. Dawkins is right when he points this out. The problem is that he stops there. For him, science is the only way to know anything.
From an experience of reality, I can logically arrive at the existence of God with a high degree of certainty. I cannot arrive at absolute certainty but I can arrive at a degree of certainty similar to that found in many of our scientific theories, i.e., knowledge characterized by a sufficiently high level of probability based on public corroboration or demonstration. Given the fact of the hackberry in my front yard, I can arrive at the existence of God through the use of a consistent, logical chain of reasoning from the reality of the tree.
So when I look at the world around me, what can I say about reality? Well the most obvious is that reality is. Things exist. The hackberry tree exists.
A second almost immediate observation is that things change. The hackberry tree sprouts leaves in the spring and sheds them in autumn. Rocks erode through the actions of water and wind. I need to re-paint my house every so often due to the weathering of the wood. Cats have kittens and dogs have puppies. Ice melts and water freezes. Etc.
In fact, I can say just about everything that exists around me changes in some way.
I also observe that things around me depend in some way on other things to maintain their existence. The hackberry tree needs sunlight and water in order for it to stay alive and whole. If I shut off its ability to access sunlight and water, the tree will soon die and eventually decay. In short, the tree will no longer exist as a tree. The existence of the tree is dependent on the sunlight and water.
Similarly, the hackberry tree depends on the cells and tissues that are contained within it. If the cells and tissues were disrupted, the tree as a tree would cease to exist.
So when I look at the universe, at reality, I see many examples of things that are dependent on other things for their existence – their existence is not necessary – they could just as easily not exist as exist – they are contingent and conditional on the existence of other things.
Chains and more chains
The tree exists. But it exists conditionally and contingently. The tree depends on the cells that make up its tissues. The cells are also contingent and conditional. The cells depend on the molecules that make up their chemical components. The molecules depend on the atoms. The atoms depend on protons. The protons depend on quarks. Etc.
So what we have is a chain of contingent and conditional existence. But what is special about this chain is that each link in the chain is at once dependent on another link for its own existence and also serves as the condition for the existence of another link.
At any moment, each link’s existence is ensured by the existence of other links in the chain – all simultaneously.
The question becomes then if the chain ever ends.
To Infinity and Beyond
One hypothesis might be that it is an infinite chain of contingent and conditional things. But this proposition must be false.
According to this hypothesis, the hackberry tree is dependent on an infinite number of conditions being sustained for its existence. There is no last condition – no fundamental conditional and contingent thing upon which the tree’s existence ultimately depends.
If there is no fundamental condition, the number of conditions upon which the hackberry tree depends is always 1 more than can be achieved. Therefore it becomes unachievable.
If the tree depends on an unachievable number of conditions for its existence, it will never exist. If the tree is dependent on a dependent on a dependent on …. to infinity in order to exist, it will never exist because all the conditions will never be met.
But the tree exists. I fetched a soccer ball out of its limbs just today. Therefore, the chain of conditions for the tree’s existence cannot be infinite.
Finitude
This leads to a second hypothesis that the chain is a finite number of conditions. If finite, then there must be a last condition or a most fundamental condition upon which the tree depends. Maybe a particle that science has yet to identify?
If this fundamental condition is a contingent and conditional thing, then as the endpoint in the chain, it would be a conditional and contingent thing whose conditions are not fulfilled. As the terminating link in the chain, there is no other condition to support it.
But a conditional and contingent thing whose conditions are not fulfilled cannot exist – is literally nothing. If the most fundamental condition is nonexistent, then the entire chain becomes nonexistent. Ultimately, the tree would not exist.
But as I said the tree does exist. Therefore, the fundamental condition must not be conditional and must not be contingent.
So the chain of conditions on which the hackberry tree depends cannot be infinite. If the chain were infinite, the tree cannot exist. But the tree exists.
So, the chain must be finite. But the finite chain of conditions on which the tree depends cannot end with a conditional and contingent thing for this last condition would have its own conditions unfulfilled. Thus, it could not exist – the chain could not exist – the tree could not exist. But the tree exists.
Therefore, there must be an unconditioned and non-contingent thing as the fundamental condition upon which the entire chain depends and upon which ultimately the tree’s existence depends.
In like manner as what I have just done, I can describe a chain of conditions for any contingent and conditional thing – a rock, a dog, a cow, an automobile, a person, etc. In each of these instances, we can arrive at a chain of conditions upon which its existence depends and that ends in a fundamental condition that is itself not contingent and not conditional.
So there cannot exist only contingent and conditional things in reality. Reality must also include at least one unconditioned and noncontigent thing.
This has been what philosophers have termed “God”.
In the next post, we'll continue down this chain of reasoning.
First, we must recognize that reality is very complicated and we must accept that we are prone to error. We must be careful not to require things to fall into neat, tidy, and easy little answers. Thinking is hard work and there are no short cuts to truth. And in our thinking, observing, and reasoning we must be consistent with the reality that is in front of us. If I start out my reasoning by denying part or all of reality, I will never reach the truth. All our knowledge, proper and improper, and all our beliefs need to be evaluated against reality. Otherwise, we are on only so many flights of fantasy whose destination is the land of unknowing – a land where each individual can determine his or her own truth, his or her own value system, and where each such truth and value system is equal to every other. (Hmmm … why does this sound so very familiar?)
Second as a means to control error, we must ground any proposition we hold in sufficient evidence to rationally prove its truth. Basically, we have three ways to do such:
1. A proposition can be affirmed by rigorous public substantiation through an agreed upon criterion which is sufficient to make a preponderance of reasonable and responsible people believe that a proposition is reasonably true – for example in science such corroboration is achieved through the repetition of experiment.
OR
2. We can show that the denial of my proposition leads to an intrinsic contradiction or impossible state of affairs.
OR
3. We can show that the denial of the proposition leads to a contradiction of publicly confirmed fact.
Only one of these is necessary to prove the truth and reasonableness of a proposition.
Third, we must be careful to clearly define terms used in our arguments and propositions. Terms should be defined so that the definitions allow for public corroboration, demonstrate non-contradiction, or demonstrate that a hypothetical proposition does not contradict a rigorously confirmed fact. The definitions of terms do not need to be all encompassing of all conditions, but the definitions do need to have sufficient meaning to successfully complete demonstration or corroboration.
Contingent and Conditional
As laid out in my previous posts, empirical science cannot prove or disprove the existence of God. Dawkins is right when he points this out. The problem is that he stops there. For him, science is the only way to know anything.
From an experience of reality, I can logically arrive at the existence of God with a high degree of certainty. I cannot arrive at absolute certainty but I can arrive at a degree of certainty similar to that found in many of our scientific theories, i.e., knowledge characterized by a sufficiently high level of probability based on public corroboration or demonstration. Given the fact of the hackberry in my front yard, I can arrive at the existence of God through the use of a consistent, logical chain of reasoning from the reality of the tree.
So when I look at the world around me, what can I say about reality? Well the most obvious is that reality is. Things exist. The hackberry tree exists.
A second almost immediate observation is that things change. The hackberry tree sprouts leaves in the spring and sheds them in autumn. Rocks erode through the actions of water and wind. I need to re-paint my house every so often due to the weathering of the wood. Cats have kittens and dogs have puppies. Ice melts and water freezes. Etc.
In fact, I can say just about everything that exists around me changes in some way.
I also observe that things around me depend in some way on other things to maintain their existence. The hackberry tree needs sunlight and water in order for it to stay alive and whole. If I shut off its ability to access sunlight and water, the tree will soon die and eventually decay. In short, the tree will no longer exist as a tree. The existence of the tree is dependent on the sunlight and water.
Similarly, the hackberry tree depends on the cells and tissues that are contained within it. If the cells and tissues were disrupted, the tree as a tree would cease to exist.
So when I look at the universe, at reality, I see many examples of things that are dependent on other things for their existence – their existence is not necessary – they could just as easily not exist as exist – they are contingent and conditional on the existence of other things.
Chains and more chains
The tree exists. But it exists conditionally and contingently. The tree depends on the cells that make up its tissues. The cells are also contingent and conditional. The cells depend on the molecules that make up their chemical components. The molecules depend on the atoms. The atoms depend on protons. The protons depend on quarks. Etc.
So what we have is a chain of contingent and conditional existence. But what is special about this chain is that each link in the chain is at once dependent on another link for its own existence and also serves as the condition for the existence of another link.
At any moment, each link’s existence is ensured by the existence of other links in the chain – all simultaneously.
The question becomes then if the chain ever ends.
To Infinity and Beyond
One hypothesis might be that it is an infinite chain of contingent and conditional things. But this proposition must be false.
According to this hypothesis, the hackberry tree is dependent on an infinite number of conditions being sustained for its existence. There is no last condition – no fundamental conditional and contingent thing upon which the tree’s existence ultimately depends.
If there is no fundamental condition, the number of conditions upon which the hackberry tree depends is always 1 more than can be achieved. Therefore it becomes unachievable.
If the tree depends on an unachievable number of conditions for its existence, it will never exist. If the tree is dependent on a dependent on a dependent on …. to infinity in order to exist, it will never exist because all the conditions will never be met.
But the tree exists. I fetched a soccer ball out of its limbs just today. Therefore, the chain of conditions for the tree’s existence cannot be infinite.
Finitude
This leads to a second hypothesis that the chain is a finite number of conditions. If finite, then there must be a last condition or a most fundamental condition upon which the tree depends. Maybe a particle that science has yet to identify?
If this fundamental condition is a contingent and conditional thing, then as the endpoint in the chain, it would be a conditional and contingent thing whose conditions are not fulfilled. As the terminating link in the chain, there is no other condition to support it.
But a conditional and contingent thing whose conditions are not fulfilled cannot exist – is literally nothing. If the most fundamental condition is nonexistent, then the entire chain becomes nonexistent. Ultimately, the tree would not exist.
But as I said the tree does exist. Therefore, the fundamental condition must not be conditional and must not be contingent.
So the chain of conditions on which the hackberry tree depends cannot be infinite. If the chain were infinite, the tree cannot exist. But the tree exists.
So, the chain must be finite. But the finite chain of conditions on which the tree depends cannot end with a conditional and contingent thing for this last condition would have its own conditions unfulfilled. Thus, it could not exist – the chain could not exist – the tree could not exist. But the tree exists.
Therefore, there must be an unconditioned and non-contingent thing as the fundamental condition upon which the entire chain depends and upon which ultimately the tree’s existence depends.
In like manner as what I have just done, I can describe a chain of conditions for any contingent and conditional thing – a rock, a dog, a cow, an automobile, a person, etc. In each of these instances, we can arrive at a chain of conditions upon which its existence depends and that ends in a fundamental condition that is itself not contingent and not conditional.
So there cannot exist only contingent and conditional things in reality. Reality must also include at least one unconditioned and noncontigent thing.
This has been what philosophers have termed “God”.
In the next post, we'll continue down this chain of reasoning.
Tuesday, October 4, 2011
God, Aquinas, and Dawkins: Is There Evidence of the Existence of God from Contemporary Physics?
The following is an excerpt from:
The Magis God Wiki: CosmologyIs there Evidence of the Existence of God from Contemporary Physics?
© Robert J. Spitzer, S.J. Ph.D./Magis Institute July 2011
Can Science Give Evidence of a Creation and Supernatural Design?
We should begin by clarifying what science can really tell us about a beginning of the universe and supernatural causation. First, unlike philosophy and metaphysics, science cannot deductively prove a creation or God. This is because natural science deals with the physical universe and with the regularities which we call “laws of nature” that are obeyed by the phenomena within that universe. But God is not an object or phenomenon or regularity within the physical universe; so science cannot say anything about God. Moreover, science is an empirical and inductive discipline. As such, science cannot be certain that it has considered all possible data that would be relevant to a complete explanation of particular physical phenomena or the universe itself. It is always open to new data and discoveries which could alter its explanation of particular phenomena and the universe. This can be seen quite clearly in revisions made to the Big Bang model.So what can science tell us? It can identify, aggregate, and synthesize evidence indicating that the finitude of past time in the universe as we currently know it to be and conceive it could be. Science can also identify the exceedingly high improbability of the random occurrence of conditions necessary to sustain life in the universe as we currently know it to be and conceive it could be.
Even though scientific conclusions are subject to modification in the light of new data, we should not let this possibility cause us to unnecessarily discount the validity of long-standing, persistent, rigorously established theories. If we did this, we might discount the majority of our scientific theories. Thus, it is reasonable and responsible to attribute qualified truth value to such theories until such time as new data requires them to be modified.
What is The Evidence for a Beginning and what are the Implications for Creation?
The arguments that suggest the finitude of past time (i.e. that time had a beginning) are basically of two types: (a) arguments about the possible geometries of spacetime and (b) arguments based on the Second Law of Thermodynamics (entropy). Though the arguments we shall give may conceivably have loopholes, in the sense that cosmological models or scenarios may be found in the future to which these arguments don’t apply, their persistence and applicability to a large number of existing cosmological models gives them respectable probative force. Until such time as they are shown to be invalid or inapplicable to empirically verifiable characteristics of our universe, they should be considered as justifying the conclusion that it is at least probable that the universe had a beginning.A Beginning in Physics Implies A Creation of the Universe
Before examining this evidence, it is essential to discuss the implications of a beginning (in physics) for a creation of our universe. A beginning in physics implies a Creator. Because a beginning in physics marks a point at which the universe came into existence. In physics, time is something real, and it has real effects on other physical phenomena. Thus, the point at which the universe comes into existence is also the point at which physical time comes into existence.How does this imply a Creator? First, in physics, nothing physical could exist prior to the beginning point (indeed there is no “prior to the beginning point” because there is no physical time).
Secondly, if the physical universe (and its physical time) did not exist prior to the beginning, then it was literally nothing. It is important to note that “nothing” means “nothing.” It does not mean a “vacuum” or “a low energy state of a quantum field,” “empty space,” or other real things. Vacuums, empty space, and low energy states in quantum fields are dimensional and orientable – they have specific characteristics and parameters, but nothing is not dimensional or orientable, and it does not have any specific characteristics or parameters because it is nothing. For example, you can have more or less of a vacuum or empty space, but you cannot have more or less of nothing because nothing is nothing.
Thirdly, nothing can do only nothing, because it is nothing. To imply the contrary is to make nothing into something. The classical expression was, “from nothing, only nothing comes.”
Fourthly, if nothing can’t do anything, then it certainly cannot create anything. Thus, when the universe was nothing, it could not have created itself (made itself into something) when it was nothing, because when it was nothing, it could only do nothing.
Finally, if the universe could not have made itself something when it was nothing, then something else would have had to have made the universe something when it was nothing, and that “something else” would have to be completely transcendent (completely independent of the universe and beyond it). This transcendent (and independent) creative force beyond our universe (and its space-time asymmetry) is generally termed “a Creator.” Therefore, a beginning in physics implies a transcendent powerful creative force (a “Creator”).
Was the Big Bang the Beginning?
In view of the fact that a beginning in physics implies a Creator, many physicists with a naturalistic orientation would like to avoid the necessity of such a beginning. For this reason, they have proposed that the big bang was not the beginning of the universe. Before we can assess this hypothesis, we will want to get a few facts about the contemporary big bang theory.The Big Bang Theory was proposed originally by a Belgium priest by the name of Fr. George Lemaitre who used it to resolve a problem (the radial velocities of extra galactic nebulae) connected with Einstein’s General Theory of Relativity. Though Einstein did not at first affirm the idea of an expanding universe, he later believed it because of its overwhelming verification. Indeed, it is one of the most rigorously established theories in physics today.
Essentially, the contemporary Big Bang Theory holds that the big bang occurred approximately 13.7 billion years ago (plus or minus 200 million years). It may be analogized to a balloon blowing up where the elastic on the balloon is like the space-time field (in general relativity, space-time can actually stretch, expand as a whole, warp, vibrate, and change its coordinate structure according to the density of mass-energy in it).
Now, going back to our analogy, suppose there are paint spots all over the balloon; notice that as the balloon expands (i.e. as space-time stretches and expands as a whole), all the paint dots (which may be likened to galaxies) move away from each other. Our universe has been doing something like this for 13.7 billion years.
Our observable universe seems to have a finite amount of mass-energy. It has approximately 4.6% visible matter (matter-energy that can emit light, electromagnetic fields, etc.), 23% dark matter (interacts with gravity, but does not seem to have luminescent or electromagnetic activity), and 72.4% dark energy (which seems to be like a field attached to a space-time field causing space-time to accelerate in its expansion). The visible matter in our universe seems to be approximately 1055 kilograms which is approximately 1080 baryons (protons and neutrons – particles with significant rest mass).
Since the time of Fr. Lemaitre, the Big Bang Theory has been confirmed by multiple, distinct data sets which come together around a similar set of numbers and values: Edwin Hubble’s’ Redshifts (which shows that all galaxies are moving away from each other), Arno Penzias’ and Robert Wilson’s discovery of the 2.7 degree Kelvin uniformly distributed radiation which is the remnant of the big bang, evidence from the cosmic background explorer satellite (COBE), and further evidence from the Wilkinson Microwave Anisotropy Probe (WMAP). This is why most physicists consider the big bang to be a rigorously established physical theory.
Was the big bang the beginning of the universe? Many physicists think that it was because the big bang was the moment at which space-time came into existence and because there is no physical evidence for a period prior to the big bang. However, some physicists believe that the big bang was not the beginning of our universe which opens the possibility for a pre-big-bang period of indefinite length (perhaps avoiding a beginning and all of its implications for a creation). This hypothetical pre-big-bang period is made possible through quantum cosmology (which allows the universe to operate in a space-time smaller than the minimums required by general relativity). Currently, string theory is one hypothetical candidate for quantum cosmology in which some physicists (including Stephen Hawking) have placed considerable hope. (Those of you interested in additional detail on quantum cosmology and string theory will want to read the Postscript to Part One of NPG). String Theory allows for the possibility of higher-dimensional space, which in turn, allows for two possible pre-big bang periods:
1. A multiverse (a mega universe which coughs out multiple bubble universes, one of which is our universe) and
2. An oscillating universe in higher dimensional space (e.g. two three dimensional membranes interacting and colliding through a four dimensional bulk space-time).
It is not important to know all the details of a multiverse or an oscillating universe in higher dimensional space, because there is only one relevant question. Do these speculative scenarios themselves require a beginning or can they go indefinitely back into the past? It so happens that a considerable amount of work has been done in the area of space-time geometry proofs which conclude that all inflationary model universes, multiverses (which must be inflationary in order to exist), and oscillating universes in higher dimensional space must have a beginning. These extraordinary proofs suggest the probability that our universe (or any multiverse in which it might be situated) must have a beginning, which implies a Creator. So what are these proofs?
Evidence of a Beginning from Space-Time Geometry Proofs
There are three pieces of evidence arising out of space-time geometry proofs which indicate a beginning of our universe or any speculative multiverse in which our universe might be situated. It also indicates a beginning of oscillating universes – even oscillating universes in higher dimensional space. These proofs are so widely applicable that they establish a beginning of virtually every hypothetical pre-big bang condition which can be connected to our universe. They, therefore, indicate the probability of an absolute beginning of physical reality which implies the probability of a Creator outside of our universe (or any multiverse in which it might be situated).Since 1994 two proofs and (and a series of models) have been developed that show that not only our universe, but any multiverse and inflationary bouncing universe must have a beginning: 1) The 1994 Borde-Vilenkin Proof, 2) The modeling of inflationary universes by Alan Guth and others, and 3) The 2003 Borde-Vilenkin-Guth Theorem (the BVG Theorem).
The 1994 Borde-Vilenkin Proof
Arvin Borde (Kavli Institute of Theoretical Physics at the University of California Santa Barbara) and Alexander Vilenkin (Director of the Institute of Cosmology at Tufts University) formulated a proof in 1994 that every inflationary universe meeting five assumptions would have to have a singularity (a beginning of the universe/multiverse in a finite proper time)[1]. Our universe meets all the conditions in this proof. In 1997 they discovered a possible exception to one of their assumptions (concerning weak energy conditions) which was very, very unlikely within our universe. Physicists, including Alan Guth (the Victor Weisskopf Professor of Physics at the Massachusetts Institute of Technology, and father of inflationary theory) did not consider this exception to be relevant: “… the technical assumption questioned in the 1997 Borde-Vilenkin paper does not seem important enough to me to change the conclusion [that the 1994 proof of a beginning of inflationary model universes is required].”[2] Therefore, the 1994 proof still has general validity today. (Refer to NPEG Chapter One, Section IV.D)Alan Guth’s 1999 analysis of expanding pre-big-bang models
Guth concluded his study as follows: “In my own opinion, it looks like eternally inflating models necessarily have a beginning… As hard as physicists have worked to try to construct an alternative, so far all the models that we construct have a beginning; they are eternal into the future, but not into the past.”[3](Refer to NPEG Chapter One, Section IV.D)
The 2003 Borde-Vilenkin-Guth Theorem (the BVG Theorem):
Borde, Vilenkin, and Guth joined together to formulate an elegant and vastly applicable demonstration of a beginning of expanding universes (in a famous article in Physical Review Letters). Alexander Vilenkin explains it as follows:“Suppose, for example, that [a] space traveler has just zoomed by the earth at the speed of 100,000 kilometers per second and is now headed toward a distant galaxy, about a billion light years away. [because of the expansion of the universe as a whole], that galaxy is moving away from us at a speed of 20,000 kilometers per second, so when the space traveler catches up with it, the observers there will see him moving at 80,000 kilometers per second. [As the universe continues to expand, the relative velocity of the space traveler will get smaller and smaller into the future]. If the velocity of the space traveler relative to the spectators gets smaller and smaller into the future, then it follows that his velocity should get larger and larger as we follow his history into the past. In the limit, his velocity should get arbitrarily close to the speed of light [the maximum velocity attainable by mass energy in the universe].”[4]The point where relative velocities become arbitrarily close to the speed of light constitutes a boundary to past time in any expanding universe or multiverse. Though the conclusion of Borde, Vilenkin, and Guth is somewhat technical for non physicists, its importance makes their precise words worth mentioning:
Our argument shows that null and time like geodesics are, in general, past-incomplete [requiring a boundary to past time] in inflationary models, whether or not energy conditions hold, provided only that the averaged expansion condition Hav > 0 hold along these past-directed geodesics. This is a stronger conclusion than the one arrived at in previous work in that we have shown under reasonable assumptions that almost all causal geodesics, when extended to the past of an arbitrary point, reach the boundary of the inflating region of space-time in a finite proper time.[5]This proof is vastly applicable to just about any model universe or multiverse that could be connected with our universe. Alexander Vilenkin put it this way in 2006:
We made no assumptions about the material content of the universe. We did not even assume that gravity is described by Einstein’s equations. So, if Einstein’s gravity requires some modification, our conclusion will still hold. The only assumption that we made was that the expansion rate of the universe never gets below some nonzero value, no matter how small. This assumption should certainly be satisfied in the inflating false vacuum. The conclusion is that past-eternal inflation without a beginning is impossible. [6]Physicists do not use the word “impossible” very often. So, Vilenkin’s claim here is quite strong. The reason he is able to make it is that there is only one condition that must be fulfilled – an expansion rate of the universe greater than zero (no matter how small).
It is important to note that Borde, Vilenkin, and Guth applied their theorem to the string multiverse as well as to higher dimensional oscillating universes. I present their own words here (which might be quite difficult for non-physicists) because it gives a sense of their own appreciation of the vast applicability of their theorem:
Our argument can be straightforwardly extended to cosmology in higher dimensions [arising out of string theory/M Theory]. For example, [1] in [some models of a string multiverse], brane worlds are created in collisions of bubbles nucleating in an inflating higher-dimensional bulk space-time. Our analysis implies that the inflating bulk cannot be past-complete [i.e. must have a boundary to past time]. ¶ [2] We finally comment on the cyclic Universe model [in the higher dimensional space of string theory] in which a bulk of four spatial dimensions is sandwiched between two three-dimensional branes…In some versions of the cyclic model the brane space-times’ are everywhere expanding, so our theorem immediately implies the existence of a past boundary at which boundary conditions must be imposed. In other versions, there are brief periods of contraction, but the net result of each cycle is an expansion.…Thus, as long as Hav > 0 for a null geodesic when averaged over one cycle, then Hav > 0 for any number of cycles, and our theorem would imply that the geodesic is incomplete [i.e. must have a boundary to past time].[7]The boundary to past time (required in the BVG theorem) could indicate an absolute beginning of the universe or a pre-pre-big bang era with a completely different physics. If it is the latter, then the pre-big-bang period would also have to have had a boundary to its past time (because it would have a rate of expansion greater than zero). Eventually, one will reach an absolute beginning when there are no more pre-pre-pre-big-bang eras.
This is an extraordinary conclusion, because it shows that a beginning is required in virtually every conceivable pre-big-bang scenario – including the string multiverse and oscillating universes in higher dimensional space. By implication, then, even if there were multiple pre-big-bang eras, it is likely that these eras would have to have an expansion rate greater than zero, which means that they too would have to have a beginning, which would make an absolute beginning virtually unavoidable. This absolute beginning would be the point at which the universe came into existence. Prior to that point the universe (and its physical time) would have been nothing, which as we saw above, implies a Creator.
Exceptions to this theorem are very difficult to formulate and are quite tenuous because they require either a universe with an average Hubble expansion less than or equal to zero (which is difficult to connect to our inflationary universe) or a deconstruction of time which is physically unrealistic. (For an extended discussion of these exceptions, you may consult Chapter One, Section III.D-E of NPEG). For this reason all attempts to get around the BVG Theorem to date have been unsuccessful. Even if physicists in the future are able to formulate a hypothetical model which could get around the BVG Theorem, it would not mean that this hypothetical model is true for our universe. It is likely to be only a testimony to human ingenuity. Therefore, it is probable that our universe (or any multiverse in which it might be situated) had an absolute beginning. This implies a creation of the universe by a Power transcending our universe.
There is another impressive set of data which corroborates the above three space-time geometry proofs, namely, the Second Law of Thermodynamics (i.e. entropy). The constraints of time will not permit me to address this topic, however, those interested in explication of it may consult Chapter One (Section III A-C) of NPEG). In conclusion, the evidence from physics (from both space-time geometry proofs and the second law of thermodynamics) indicates the probability of a beginning of our universe. In as much as a beginning indicates a point at which our universe came into existence, and prior to that point, the universe was nothing, then it is probable that the universe (and any hypothetical multiverse in which it might be situated) was created by a transcendent power outside of physical space and time.
Implications of Supernatural Intelligence in the Fine-tuning of Universal Constants
There are several conditions of our universe necessary for the emergence of any complex life form. Many of these conditions are so exceedingly improbable that it is not reasonable to expect that they could have occurred by pure chance For this reason many physicists attribute their occurrence to supernatural design. Some other physicists prefer to believe instead in trillions upon trillions of “other universes” (which are unobserved and likely unobservable). Before discussing which explanation is more probative, we need to explore some specific instances of this highly improbable fine-tuning. We may break the discussion into two parts:1. The exceedingly high improbability of our low entropy universe, and
2. The exceedingly high improbability of the anthropic values of our universe’s constants.
We will discuss each in turn.
The high improbability of a pure chance occurrence of our low-entropy universe
A low-entropy universe is necessary for the emergence, development, and complexification of life forms (because a high entropy universe would be too run down to allow for such development). Roger Penrose has calculated the exceedingly small probability of a pure chance occurrence of our low–entropy universe as 10^10^123 to one. How can we understand this number? It is like a ten raised to an exponent of:100000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000.
This number is so large, that if every zero were 10 point type, our solar system would not be able to hold it! Currently, there is no natural explanation for the occurrence of this number, and if none is found, then we are left with the words of Roger Penrose himself:
“In order to produce a universe resembling the one in which we live, the Creator would have to aim for an absurdly tiny volume of the phase space of possible universes—about 1/10^10^123 of the entire volume, for the situation under consideration.”What Penrose is saying here is that this occurrence cannot be explained by a random (pure chance) occurrence. Therefore, one will have to make recourse either to a multiverse (composed of bubble universes, each having different values of constants) or as Penrose implies, a Creator (with a super-intellect).
The high improbability of five other anthropic conditions (based on cosmological constants)
A cosmological constant is a number which controls the equations of physics, and the equations of physics, in turn, describe the laws of nature. Therefore, these numbers control the laws of nature (and whether these laws of nature will be hospitable or hostile to any life form). Some examples of constants are: the speed of light constant (c= 300,000 km per second), Planck’s constant (ℏ = 6.6 x 10-34 joule seconds), the gravitational attraction constant (G = 6.67 x 10-11 ), the strong nuclear force constant (gs = 15), the weak force constant (gw = 1.43 x 10-62), the mass of the proton (mp = 1.67 x 10-27 kg), rest mass of an electron (me = 9.11 x 10-31 kg), and charge of an electron proton (e = 1.6 x 10-19 coulombs). There are several other constants, but these pertain to the following anthropic coincidences (highly improbable conditions required for life).(i) If the gravitational constant (G) or weak force constant (gw) varied from their values by an exceedingly small fraction (higher or lower) -- one part in 10^50 (.00000000000000000000000000000000000000000000000001) then either the universe would have suffered a catastrophic collapse or would have exploded throughout its expansion, both of which options would have prevented the emergence and development of any life form. This cannot be reasonably explained by pure chance.
(ii) If the strong nuclear force constant were higher than its value (15) by only 2%, there would be no hydrogen in the universe (and therefore no nuclear fuel or water -- this would have prohibited life). If, on the other hand, the strong nuclear force constant had been 2% lower than its value then no element heavier than hydrogen could have emerged in the universe (helium, carbon, etc). This would have been equally detrimental to the development of life. This “anthropic coincidence” also seems to lie beyond the boundaries of pure chance.
(iii) If the gravitational constant, electromagnetism, or the “proton mass relative to the electron mass” varied from their values by only a tiny fraction (higher or lower), then all stars would be either blue giants or red dwarfs. These kinds of stars would not emit the proper kind of heat and light for a long enough period to allow for the emergence, development, and complexification of life forms. Again, these “anthropic coincidences” are beyond pure chance occurrence.
(iv) If the weak force constant had been slightly smaller or larger than its value, then supernovae explosions would never have occurred. If these explosions had not occurred, there would be no carbon, iron, or earth-like planets.
(v) Fred Hoyle and William Fowler discovered the exceedingly high improbability of oxygen, carbon, helium and beryllium having the precise values to allow for both carbon abundance and carbon bonding (necessary for life). This “anthropic coincidence” was so striking that it caused Hoyle to abandon his previous atheism and declare:
“A common sense interpretation of the facts suggests that a superintellect has monkeyed with physics, as well as with chemistry and biology, and that there are no blind forces worth speaking about in nature. The numbers one calculates from the facts seem to me so overwhelming as to put this conclusion almost beyond question.”(For all five “anthropic coincidences,” refer to NPEG Chapter One, Sect. II and Lectures #5 and 6 of PID.)
The odds against all five of the anthropic coincidences happening randomly is so exceedingly improbable that it is like telling a monkey to type out the corpus of Shakespeare perfectly by random tapping of the keys. After returning two weeks later the entire corpus of Shakespeare, Hamlet, Macbeth, Richard III, are all perfectly recounted. Most reasonable and responsible individuals would not attribute this to random occurrence (because the odds are so overwhelmingly against it), and so, they look for another explanation which is more reasonable and responsible.
For this reason, no respectable physicist (including Stephen Hawking), believes that these anthropic coincidences can be explained by pure chance. In view of the fact that no natural explanation has been found for them, most physicists have made recourse to two trans-universal explanations:
1. A multiverse (a naturalistic explanation) and
2. A super intellectual Creator (a supernatural explanation).
Is the naturalistic explanation more reasonable and responsible? Not necessarily because the other universes (and the multiverse itself) are in principle unobservable. Furthermore, it violates the principle of parsimony (Ockham’s Razor) – the explanation with the least number of assumptions, conditions, and requirements is to be preferred. As Paul Davies notes:
Another weakness of the anthropic argument is that it seems the very antithesis of Ockham’s razor, according to which the most plausible of a possible set of explanations is that which contains the simplest ideas and least number of assumptions. To invoke an infinity of other universes just to explain one is surely carrying excess baggage to cosmic extremes … It is hard to see how such a purely theoretical construct can ever be used as an explanation, in the scientific sense, of a feature of nature. Of course, one might find it easier to believe in an infinite array of universes than in an infinite Deity, but such a belief must rest on faith rather than observation.[8]3. All known multiverse theories have significant fine-tuning requirements. Linde’s chaotic inflationary multiverse cannot randomly cough out bubble universes because they would collide and make both universes inhospitable to life; the bubble universes must be spaced out in a slow roll which requires considerable fine-tuning in the multiverses initial parameters.[9] Similarly, Susskind’s String Theory landscape requires considerable meta-level fine-tuning to explain its “anthropic" tendencies.[10]
Conclusions
Given these problems, is the multiverse a more reasonable and responsible explanation of our universe’s anthropic coincidences? Many physicists believe that it is not, not only because of the above three problems, but also because of the likelihood of a Creator. When the evidence for a beginning (a Creator) is combined with the exceedingly high improbability of the above anthropic coincidences, a super intellect may be the most reasonable and responsible explanation because it avoids all the problems of a hypothetical multiverse. Thus, it is both reasonable and responsible to believe on the basis of physics, that there is a very powerful and intelligent being that caused our universe to exist as a whole.Footnotes
Friday, July 8, 2011
God, Aquinas, and Dawkins: God is Not a Hypothesis
In Chapters 2-4, Dawkins lays out the heart of his arguments against the “God Hypothesis”. Chapters 2-3 involve his refutation of the traditional arguments used to show the existence of God. He particularly takes aim at the 5 ways of Aquinas as well as the Ontological Argument. Chapter 4, by his own admission, is the most critical chapter in the book in which he attempts to conclusively refute the existence of God by arguing against “intelligent design” and showing how evolution by natural selection proves that any reference to God or divine intervention/creation is foolish.
In the later chapters of the book, Dawkins attempts to offer an evolutionary explanation of the development of religion among humans. He also seeks to show how a system of ethics can be worked out without reference to any divinity or religious system.
It’s Evolutionary! - No Argument from Me!
Dawkins is a brilliant evolutionary biologist – a noted expert in his field of study. He is more than able to discuss evolutionary theory. I will not be refuting evolutionary theory. I will not argue the relative merits and deficits of the theory. In fact, I have no problem personally, intellectually, or even religiously with evolutionary theory. Evolution by natural selection is quite clearly a fact of the natural world. The overall theory is valid even if the nuance of detail is open to debate. I won’t be entering that debate.
Who Needs a Brain? – Oh Yeah, That Man Made of Straw!
Additionally throughout the book, Dawkins repeatedly sets up “straw men” and then proceeds to engage in ad hominem attacks on the very straw men he has devised. Examples of this abound. However there are two that I find worth noting at this point. First, Dawkins lays out his understanding/definition/description of God especially as he understands (or more accurately misunderstands) the God revealed in the bible. He particularly has choice invectives for the “God of the Old Testament”. Second, Dawkins hurls malediction and invective at religion itself – identifying it and equating it to disease, corruption, and evil.
For the moment, I won’t be entering this debate either. I am certain that the highly provocative and aggressive language used by Dawkins in these ad hominem attacks is a true reflection of his core beliefs and values. The strength of his passion in these remarks is, at times, quite remarkable. But I view these remarks as incidental to the main points he is trying to make.
The simple fact is that his main premises are irrational, illogical, and erroneous. They do not meet the criteria of sound rational argumentation and it is the oldest trick in the book to use invective, personal attack, and highly charged emotional language to somehow compensate for poorly constructed argumentation.
Such language also sells more books.
So What’s Your Point(s)?
In the next few posts, I will address what I perceive to be the book’s major points. My basic premises are as follows:
- · The scientific method cannot conclusively prove that God does or does not exist;
- · From an experience of reality, I can logically arrive at the existence of God with a high degree of certainty (but not absolute).
- · The theory of evolution does not necessarily entail any particular atheistic, agnostic, or Christian understanding of the world.
- · Dawkins’ refutation of William Paley’s watchmaker analogy does not equate to a refutation of God’s existence because “intelligent design” itself does not hold water.
- · Dawkins’ proposal that ‘memes’ explain the evolutionary development of human culture is itself as illogical and unscientific as his description of religion is.
- · There is a very real part of the human being that transcends the physical and material.
- · Natural law provides the basis for all human ethical behavior.
Let’s Be Clear Here!
An important point needs to be made here.
All our knowledge, proper and improper, and all our beliefs need to be evaluated against reality. Einstein warned that even as coherent, clear, and attractive his theory of general relativity was, its true worth would only be determined by experiment and observation (i.e. the real world). There is a temptation to sacrifice reality for clarity or elegance of thought. We must recognize that reality is very complicated and accept that we are prone to error. Aquinas states that mathematics is much more connatural to us than philosophy and it is much harder for us to reach certainty in philosophy than in mathematics. Hence we must be careful to not require things to fall into a type of study that is easiest for us and thus most clear to us. In other words, thinking is hard work – there are no short cuts to the truth – and we must always be consistent with the reality in front of us. I can create the most elegant and eloquent systems of thought but if it is not the result of a consistent, logical chain of reasoning from the reality of the universe – it is only so much smoke and mirrors. If I start out by denying part or all of reality, I cannot reach the truth. This is the problem with many modern schools of philosophy and such denials are the basis of much of the error we find in the world today. But that’s for another post on another day.
What is meant by the term “God”?
To facilitate progress I will describe what I am referring to through the use of the term “God”. The attributes that I describe here can be arrived at through a chain of logical reasoning beginning with the reality of the universe around me. I will simply describe them here in an effort to facilitate progress towards filling out my arguments for the premises I stated above. I am describing the God of the philosophers not the God of revelation. This is what we can know from reason alone – not from scripture and/or religious teaching – although the two are mutually inclusive, the one represents a starting point, a foundation if you will – or as Aquinas states, “The existence of God and other like truths about God, which can be known by natural reason, are not articles of faith, but are preambles to the articles”.
God:
1. Is Eternal
2. Has no potentiality – is complete actuality
3. Has no composition – Is Undivided Unity - simplicity
4. Is incorporeal – immaterial
5. Is pure being – existence and essence are the same
6. Has no accidents (no nonessential attributes) – includes no changeable or perishable attributes
7. Cannot be categorized into any genus or species
8. Is universal perfection
9. Is infinite
10. Is omnipresent
11. Is immutable
12. Is omnipotent
13. Is omniscient
14. Is truth itself
15. Is all good
The proposition “God exists” is not Self Evident.
Obviously, the existence of God is not at all self evident.
A proposition is self-evident because the predicate is included in the essence of the subject. An example would be “Man is an animal”. “Animal-ness” is contained in the essence of “man”.
If the essences of the predicate and subject are known to all, the proposition will be self-evident to all. If everyone understands the meaning of “man” and the meaning of “animal”, then the statement that “man is an animal” is self-evident.
If a proposition is truly self-evident, no one can mentally admit its opposite (e.g., Man is not an animal).
The opposite of “God is” can be admitted. In fact, many do admit that “God is not”. Therefore, the existence of God is not self-evident.
God is not a hypothesis because God cannot be tested experimentally
God is infinite. Because of this, I can prove God’s existence through formal logic, but I cannot empirically prove it.
I am finite, as our all humans by definition. This means that my senses are finite. The power of my observation is finite. Because of my finitude, I would be unable to observe the infinite even if it were presented to me.
I may be able to verify the infinite through formal logical analysis – for example I may be able to verify Cantor’s theory of infinite sets logically – but I cannot empirically prove such a thing. Infinity is not graspable, even in principle, by the senses.
The physical universe itself is not infinite so I have no example in the physical universe for my senses to operate on. And even if the physical universe were infinite, I still would not be able to observe its infinity – my finite senses would be incapable of taking in such infinity.
Indeed, the universe may very well be infinite, but if it is, I wouldn't be able to tell. Only my mind is able to accept the idea of infinity. My senses are unable to accept its reality. Infinity is not subject to empiricism.
Because God is infinite, this conclusion would also apply to God. God could be standing right in front of me, but I wouldn't be able to empirically observe God because my senses are finite.
Indeed, the universe may very well be infinite, but if it is, I wouldn't be able to tell. Only my mind is able to accept the idea of infinity. My senses are unable to accept its reality. Infinity is not subject to empiricism.
Because God is infinite, this conclusion would also apply to God. God could be standing right in front of me, but I wouldn't be able to empirically observe God because my senses are finite.
The scientific method cannot conclusively prove or disprove the existence of God. There is no scientific apparatus, no computer model, no point of observation from which I can empirically observe or test the infinite.
Other Arguments Against the Existence of God
At this point, the reader may say along with Dawkins,
“Of course God’s existence cannot be proven by science. Because the existence of God is a matter of faith and faith or belief is an assent to a proposition based on an authority. Believers were raised by parents who believed in God or were part of churches that believed in God. They were indoctrinated and because of the authority of parents, priests, rabbis, ministers, etc. they “believe” in God. But as you say – no one can see God; no one can observe God; no one can empirically prove God – so this faith is in an unseen, invisible something. You might as well be talking about Santa Claus or the Easter Bunny. Even belief – if it is believing a truth – must be based in reality. But we cannot be sure that God exists or not.”
“And besides almost everything we experience in the universe can be explained by science. The physical universe operates according to scientific laws and principles. And human events can be explained by human psychology, sociology, anthropology and medicine. We don’t need to suppose there is a God to make sense of the world or to make sense of human life. God is irrelevant – doesn’t matter if God exists or not.”
“Finally, believers always say that God is all good and all powerful. But there is a great deal of evil and suffering in the world. Innocent children develop deadly diseases. Natural disasters kill thousands of innocent people. So if God exists, either God is not good because God allows evil in the world. Or God is not all powerful because God cannot stop the evil. Couldn’t an all powerful and all good God create a world where there is no suffering or evil? Since there is evil and suffering in the world, there must not be a God – at least the kind of God believers talk about. Besides all this, much of the evil and suffering in the world has been done in the name of God and religion. People have been killing each other for centuries because of religion. In fact, religion is the number one cause of evil, violence, and suffering in the world.”
Ever Ancient, Ever New
My initial response to this hypothetical reader is to congratulate him or her on recapitulating the three most powerful arguments against the existence of God. They are also ancient, having roots in the philosophies of ancient Greece, and indeed restated in the 13th century by Aquinas – some 400 years prior to the birth of modern science and 700 years prior to the appearance of Dawkins!
There really is nothing new under the sun!
Tuesday, June 28, 2011
God, Aquinas, and Dawkins: The Three Ages of Science
The Three Ages of Science.
The historical development of science can be divided into three stages in two different ways, within science itself and also against the background of the beliefs of society.Within science, we can distinguish three distinct views of the world, as an organism, as a mechanism and as a mathematical formalism. The ancient Greeks, anxious to preserve human values, viewed the world as an organism, but this was a failure. In the Renaissance, when science came to maturity with Newton, the world became a mechanism, following precise mathematical equations. If we know the initial conditions, these enable us to calculate all subsequent motions, and the results are in precise agreement with our measurements. Finally, in the present century, mechanistic physics proved inadequate, and now for much of our work, we rely mainly on the mathematical equations, although physical understanding is still essential.
The relation between science and the society in which it lives also passes through three stages. In the first stage, most of the beliefs about the material world prevented or hindered the growth of science. Eventually science struggled into existence in the High Middle Ages when the Christian beliefs about the world provided the necessary conditions for its birth. It came to maturity in the Renaissance, and at that time most of the pioneer scientists were believing Christians who saw their work as showing forth the glory of God. At this point science became an autonomous self-sustaining enterprise that develops in accord with its own internal criteria, although it was still within a broadly Christian society. It needed the material support of society, and the relations between science and society were not always smooth. There have been from the beginning tensions between the scientists on the one hand and the theologians, the Church and the State authorities on the other, and among scientists between Christians and secularists. These can be a stimulating and healthy tensions, but they often degenerate into mutual incomprehension and hostility. Examples abound: Luther and Melanchthon attacked the Copernican theory, and Galileo was punished for his views. Nowadays the tension continues: many theologians are apprehensive of science, scientists like Hawking and Dawkins attack and pour scorn on theology, and there are continual battles with Government agencies to obtain sufficient support for scientific research.
In the present century we have moved into the third stage, when science more and more frequently finds itself in a society that is no longer broadly Christian, but indifferent or anti-Christian, either in its ideological roots or through the authority of the State. Science has spread rapidly over the world to non-Christian societies, as people become aware of its technological applications. But there is an important distinction; technology is easily exported and readily welcomed, but science is extremely difficult to export. Schools and universities all over the world teach science, but in most cases this has proved rather difficult, and it is not at all easy to establish really fruitful research programmes. Twice in Europe science has come under totalitarian regimes that have treated science as a slave or as a god, in Nazi Germany and in Soviet Russia. In both cases the effect on science has been disastrous, and science withered. Can science survive in a post-Christian society?
References
J. Barbour, Absolute or Relative Motion: 1. The Discovery of Dynamics. Cambridge, 1989.E.A. Burtt, The Metaphysical Foundations of Modern Physical Science . Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1932
S. Chandrasekhar, Truth and Beauty. Chicago, 1990.
R. Feynman, Surely You're Joking, Mr. Feynman?
A.R. Hall, The Scientific Revolution 1500-1800. Longmans, 1954.
G. Holton, Thematic Origins of Scientific Thought: Kepler to Einstein. Harvard, 1973.
A. Koestler, The Watershed: A Biography of Johannes Kepler. Doubleday, 1959.
D.C. Lindberg, The Beginnings of Western Science. Chicago, 1992.
W.R. Shea, Galileo's Intellectual Revolution. Science History Publications, 1977.
C.S. Singleton (Ed), Art, Science and History in the Renaissance. Johns Hopkins Press, Baltimore, 1967.
R.S. Westfall, Never at Rest: A Biography of Isaac Newton. Cambridge, 1980.
God, Aquinas, and Dawkins: The Christian Origin of Science
The Christian Origin of Science
During the Middle Ages, the thought of Europe was moulded and dominated by Christian theology and philosophy. It is therefore interesting to see how the beliefs that we have seen are necessary for science are related to Christian beliefs about the world. There is indeed a close relation between them, so Christian theology prepared the way for science by teaching that particular attitude to the world that provides the basis of science.We can see this by recalling the beliefs already listed. The Christian believes that the world is good because God made it so: "And God saw all that He had made, and indeed it was very good" (Genesis 1.31). Matter was further ennobled by the Incarnation: "The Word was made flesh and he lived among us" (John 1.14). The world is rational and orderly because it is made and kept in being by a rational God. It is contingent because it depends on the divine fiat: God could have chosen to make the world in a different way. There is here a delicate balance between the freedom and the rationality of God: tip the balance one way or the other and you have a belief in a chaotic or a necessary world, both inimical to the growth of science. Finally the Christian believes that the world can be apprehended by the human mind because God commanded man to subdue the earth, and he does not command the impossible: "Be fruitful, multiply, fill the earth and conquer it. Be masters of the fish of the sea, the birds of heaven and all living animals on the earth" (Genesis 1.28). Thus the Christian mind is steeped through and through with the beliefs about the material world that are necessary for the development of science.
The Christian also has the strongest motivation to study the world. Christ himself reiterates the divine command to subdue the earth when by the parable of the talents he urges us to make full use of all our faculties and powers. Furthermore, as soon as it becomes clear that scientific knowledge can be applied to grow more food and improve his medical care, to provide better clothes and housing, it becomes a special obligation on man to do this in view of the injunction to feed the hungry, to give drink to the thirsty and to clothe the naked.
The remaining condition for the development of science, the belief that knowledge must be freely shared, is enjoined by the Book of Wisdom: "What I have learned without self-interest, I pass on without reserve; I do not intend to hide her riches. For she is an inexhaustible treasure to men, and those who acquire it win God's friendship" (Wisdom 7.13-14). The Book of Wisdom also contains the declaration that the Creator ordered everything in measure, number and weight (11.20), the most frequently quoted Biblical phrase in medieval times.
We thus find that during the critical centuries before the birth of science the collective mind of Europe was moulded by a system of beliefs that included just those special elements that are necessary for the birth and growth of science. There is thus a living organic continuity between the Christian revelation and modern science. Christianity provided just those beliefs about the material world that are essential for science, and the moral climate that encouraged its growth.
It might however be said that the medieval origin of science is just a historical coincidence: how can we know that there is a real causal influence operating? This can indeed be found if we examine the work of some of the philosophers of the Middle Ages.
At that time the prevailing ideas of the nature of the world were derived from the Greek philosopher Aristotle. He believed in the eternity of the world, in a cyclic universe and in a world of purpose even in material things. He also believed that celestial matter, the world of the stars and the planets, is incorruptible, unlike terrestrial matter that can undergo change. These beliefs in effect prevented the development of science for two thousand years, This stranglehold had to be broken before science could develop into its modern form.
So great was the prestige of Aristotle that the philosophers of the medieval schools taught by commenting on his texts. Some of Aristotle's teaching, however, was inconsistent with the Christian faith, and the philosophers did not hesitate to differ from Aristotle when it seemed necessary. In 1215 the Fourth Lateran Council decreed that all creation, spiritual and material, took place out of nothing and in time. This is directly contrary to Aristotle's belief in the eternity of the world accepted as a self-evident truth. There was intense discussion on a variety of topics, notably concerning the creation of the world and the motion of bodies. In 1277 the bishop of Paris, Etienne Tempier, found it necessary to condemn 219 philosophical propositions as contrary to the Christian belief. His main purpose was to defend God's absolute power against any attempt by the Aristotelian philosophers to set limits to it. Several of the condemned propositions set limits to God's power, saying for instance that He cannot make more than one world or to move the world so as to produce a vacuum. Tempier thus reasserted the belief that God can freely create any world, just as He chooses. This was a turning point in the history of thought, as it liberated philosophers from bondage to Aristotle and channelled philosophical speculations about motion in a direction that led eventually to the destruction of Aristotelian physics, thus opening the way to modern science.
The theology of divine omnipotence had important consequences for the development of science as a result of Aquinas' distinction between God's absolute and ordained powers. God always has absolute power over all things, but he endows the natural world with specific natures, according to His plan for creation. These normally determine the behaviour of natural phenomena. It thus becomes a reasonable activity to try to find out about the world. Normally, by virtue of God's ordained power, the natural world strictly follows God's laws, and yet this does not prevent God from doing whatever he chooses by virtue of his absolute power. This reinforces the stability of nature as a sign of God's faithfulness so frequently expressed in the Old Testament (Jer 31:35-36; 33:25-26), while leaving open the possibility of miracles.
One of the medieval philosophers, Jean Buridan, was particularly interested in the nature of motion. This is the most fundamental problem of physics, and so if science is to begin it must begin here. In full consistency with his belief in creation, he wrote that 'God, when He created the world, moved each of the celestial orbs as he pleased, and in moving them He impressed upon them impetuses which moved them without Him having to move them any more except by the method of general influence whereby He concurs as co-agent in all things which take place'.
This shows a clear break with Aristotle, who required the continuing action of the mover throughout the motion. What Buridan called impetus was later refined into the concept of momentum, and the idea in the above passage became Newton's first law of motion. Buridan's works were widely published and his ideas became known throughout Europe, and in particular to Leonardo da Vinci and hence to the scientists of Renaissance times.
The Christian belief in the creation of the world by God also undermined Aristotle's sharp distinction between celestial and terrestrial matter. Since they are both created, why should they be different? Indeed, Buridan illustrated his concept of impetus with reference to the long jump; thus implicitly presupposing that celestial and terrestrial motions are similar. This made it possible for Newton to see that the same force that pulls an apple to the ground also keeps the moon in its orbit.
A vital component in the rise of science is the belief in the order of the world, that is the idea that every event is the precise result of preceding events. This implies that whatever measurements we make should correspond exactly, that is within the uncertainties of measurement, with our theories. A corollary is that if we want to test out theories we should make the most accurate measurements we can. This insistence on precision is essential for the progress of science, and it was made possible by the strong belief in the order of nature. It led Whitehead to say, in his Lowell lectures in 1925 on Science and the Modern World that 'the Middle Ages formed one long training of the intellect of Western Europe in the sense of order.' This by itself is not enough,and he went on:
I do not think that I have even yet brought out the greatest contribution of medievalism to the formation of the scientific movement. I mean the inexpungable belief that every detailed occurrence can be correlated with its antecedents in a perfectly definite manner, exemplifying general principles. Without this belief the incredible labours of scientists would be without hope. It is this instinctive conviction, vividly poised before the imagination, which is the motive power of research: -- that there is a secret, a secret which can be unveiled.
He went on to ask how was this conviction so vividly implanted on the European mind, and concluded: 'My explanation is that the faith in the possibility of science, generated antecedently to the development of modern scientific theory, is an unconscious derivative from medieval theology.' One might indeed query whether unconscious is the right word, for many of the medievals explicitly saw their work as showing forth the works of the Creator. Furthermore, explicitly Christian beliefs played a decisive part in making modern science possible. Thus the debilitating belief in a cyclic universe was decisively broken by the Christian belief in the uniqueness of the Incarnation. Henceforth history was no longer an infinite series of dreary cycles, but a linear story with a beginning and an end.
The transition from Greek to modern physics has been graphically described by Pierre Duhem: 'The demolition of Aristotelian physics was not a sudden collapse; the construction of modern physics did not take place on a terrain where nothing was left standing. From one to the other the passage takes place by a long sequence of partial transformations of which each pretended to retouch or enlarge some piece of the edifice without changing anything of the ensemble. But when all these modifications of detail had been made, the human mind perceived, as it sized up with a single look the result of all that long work, that nothing remained of that ancient palace and that a new palace rose in its place. Those who in the sixteenth century took stock of this substitution of one science for another were seized by a strange illusion. They imagined that this substitution was sudden and that it was their work. They proclaimed that Peripatetic physics had just collapsed under their blows and that on the ruins of that physics they had built, as if by magic, the clear abode of truth. About the sincere illusion of arrogantly wilful error of these men, the men of subsequent centuries were either the unsuspecting victims or sheer accomplices. The physicists of the sixteenth century were celebrated as creators to whom the world owed the renaissance of science. They were very often but continuers and sometimes plagiarisers.'
The Work of Pierre Duhem
These Christian roots of modern science are not generally known. The man primarily responsible for uncovering the evidence for the Christian origin of science was the French physicist Pierre Duhem. He was a theoretical physicist working mainly in the field of thermodynamics, but had always been interested in the history of physics. He was asked to write a series of articles on the history of mechanics, and easily wrote the first one on the ideas of the ancient Greeks. Like most historians of science, he expected to pass rapidly over the Middle Ages to the giants of the Renaissance. But he was a careful man, not content to rely on secondhand sources. He found obscure references to earlier work, and following them up, primarily in the archives in Paris, he discovered the work of Buridan and his pupil Orseme, and of many other medievals who contributed to the origin of science.Duhem wrote two volumes on the history of mechanics, three on Leonardo da Vinci, and then began a monumental account of the history of science in several volumes, the Systeme du Monde. The first volume, devoted to the Greeks, was published in 1913, and was highly praised by George Sarton, the founder and editor of the journal Isis, who said that he looked forward eagerly to the second volume. When however he read the second volume, he realised what Duhem had found was highly uncongenial to his secularist beliefs. Duhem left him in no doubt whatever. Writing on the doctrine of the Great Year, the belief that history continually repeats itself, he said: 'To the construction of that system all disciples of Hellenic philosophy -- Peripatetics, Stoics, Neo-Platonists -- contributed; to that system Abu Masar offered the homage of the Arabs; the most illustrious rabbis, from Philo of Alexandria to Maimonides, have accepted it. To condenm it and to throw it overboard as a monstrous superstition, Christianity had to come.'
Sarton did not try to refute Duhem; that would have been impossible. Instead he used the one remaining weapon, that of silence. None of the following volumes was reviewed in Isis, and the name of Duhem was thereafter hardly ever mentioned. In Sarton's own vast volumes on the history of science Duhem receives but a few mentions, whereas quite minor figures receive extensive discussion.
Tragically, Duhem died in 1916 when only five volumes of his Systeme du Monde, had been published. Duhem left the text of the remaining five volumes in MSS, and the publisher was bound by the terms of the contract to publish them in successive years. The secularist establishment however was bitterly opposed to their publication, and succeeded in preventing this for forty years. Only the death of his most determined opponent, and the threat of legal action, finally forced the publishers to act.
It is not surprising that secularists should be so determined to prevent the publication of books of massive scholarship that completely undermine their view of the development of science, and show that science as we know it is built on Christian foundations. What is surprising is that Christians have been so slow to recognise and to publish his work. Even today, after many decades of scholarly work on medieval science, the name of Duhem is hardly known outside specialist circles. It deserves to be familiar to all Christians, particularly those concerned with the education of the young, who are still taught that there is a fundamental opposition between science and the Christian faith.
Science in Eastern Christendom
This explanation of the rise of science in Western Europe during the High Middle Ages as due to the beliefs concerning the material world inherent in Christian theology raises the question why it happened in Western Europe and not in Eastern Europe, where Christianity also flourishes. One might indeed have expected science to arise first in the east, because it was the heir to the wisdom of ancient Greece, preserved and to some extent developed by Arab scholars. Thus from the eighth to the fourteenth centuries mathematics, astronomy, optics, physics and medicine were far more developed in Islamic countries than in Western Europe. In one vital area, for example, Arabic astronomers had so improved the Ptolemaic system that it was mathematically equivalent to the Copernican system, although it was still geocentric. And yet the lead was lost in one area after another as the West surged ahead and Arabic science decayed. This learning came to the West not via Eastern Christendom, but mainly through translations from the Arabic made in Spain. The Byzantine scientific tradition lacked originality, being content with the achievements of the Greeks and the Romans. They were thus unable to develop technology and to apply their theoretical knowledge for practical purposes.Could the explanation of the difference between the vitality of science in the West and its virtual absence in the East be due to a difference between Eastern and Western theologies, or are there other explanations, perhaps in terms of sociological factors, which themselves may or may not have their origin in theology?
The theological beliefs of Eastern and Western Christendom are essentially the same, but there are important differences at the conceptual and practical levels. These differences are difficult to describe, because there are many counter-examples to any general statement that can be made. Thus both attach high value to reason and to prayer, but the emphasis is different. In the West, scholarly work is itself considered to be a form of prayer. Orders of friars, such as the Dominicans, were founded to preach, and to teach in schools and in universities, and their times of prayer are regulated to allow time for study. Dominicans such as Thomas Aquinas taught in the universities and used reason to find out what they could about God, thus developing scholastic theology. In the monasteries of the east, the monks spend long hours in prayer, but as a result they have less time for study and for writing.
Of great importance for the origin of science is the concept of time. Before the advent of science our activities followed biological time, governed by the natural processes of night and day, the phases of the moon and the progression of the seasons. In contrast, scientific time is a regular sequence, and to each instant there corresponds a number, measurable to high accuracy. Monasteries need to have a way of marking the time to regulate the hours of prayer and work and initially they followed biological time, supplemented by sand and water clocks. In the Western monasteries, clocks of high sophistication were developed as early as the twelfth century, whereas clocks, imported from the West, were not used on Mount Athos until the eighteenth century. Even now, the east has a more relaxed sense of time.
The use of biological time is associated with primitive technology, whereas more developed technology comes with scientific time. Thus the larger western monasteries made many technological advances for domestic and industrial purposes, such as water mills and saws. This is of crucial importance for the development of science.
There are also several sociological reasons why science arose in the west and not in the east. It is essential for creative intellectual work that there are places where it can be carried on without external interference, so that the people there are free to think what they like and to follow wherever their reason leads them. Such opportunities are provided by universities, and many were founded in the West from the twelfth century onwards. The crucial steps that led to the birth of modern science took place in the university of Paris.
In the east, there was a spectacular intellectual and artistic revival in the ninth century after the end of the iconoclastic controversy, and the university of Constantinople attracted many distinguished scholars. There was, however, little interest in science or technology.
Byzantine society was rigidly authoritarian, with Church and State closely linked. The Emperor was considered the vicegerent of God, and as ruler of both church and state his word was law. There was a highly centralised state organisation with a well-developed civil service, so that practically all activities were controlled by the Emperor. Trade and commerce were rigidly controlled, not to serve the interests of the merchants but to subordinate economic life to the interests of the state. There were indeed schools, but they did not encourage independent discussion, and the static conception of life was not conducive to the development of science. In the west, on the other hand, the universities were centres of intellectual discussions, where novel views were expounded and discussed.
People speak and discuss freely when they are personally secure, when they know that they can say what they like without danger of any kind. This security can be provided by belonging to an organisation, such as a university, which encourages free discussions, or by a society that respects the right of private property. In the west this is legally established, whereas in the east property was held subject to the will of the ruler, and may at any time be revoked. If one lives in perpetual fear that the ruler will suddenly take away one's house, one is hardly likely to indulge in any activity that may incur his wrath.
In the twelfth century the Crusaders caused consternation in Byzantium as they passed through on their way to the Holy Land, exacerbating the age-old tensions between east and west. These came to a head with the sack of Constantinople in 1204. Byzantium survived another two hundred years, but was fatally weakened and finally fell to the Turks in 1453.
Such sociological factors are sufficient to explain why science did not arise in Eastern Christendom, and it seems that these are more important than any theological differences.
An instructive example of the effect of sociological factors on intellectual activity is provided by the contrast between the English, French and Spanish colonies in north and central America on the one hand, and the Dutch colony in South Africa on the other. In America, there was from the first a thriving intellectual activity, with printing presses and newspapers, and great Colleges and universities were founded within a few decades of the arrival of the colonists. Mexico was conquered in 1521, and by 1553 had a university. In North America, the colonists arrived in 1619, and Harvard was founded in 1636. In South Africa, on the other hand, everything was controlled by the Dutch East India Company, and profit was the only motive. There were no printing presses, newspapers, colleges or universities. The Church was also partly to blame for this situation, because they insisted that their ministers be trained in Holland, and were not willing to establish Colleges in South Africa.
Islam and Science
The wisdom of ancient Greece was transmitted to Europe by the Arabs. They saved and copied the Greek manuscripts, and published extensive commentaries on them. It was just these works of the Greeks that had such a seminal influence on the Middle Ages and profoundly modified European thought. The Arabs made important advances in may areas, notably in algebra, optics and ophthalmology. From the eighth to the fourteenth centuries, astronomy, optics, physics and medicine were far more developed in Islamic countries than in Western Europe. Arabic astronomers, to take one instance, had so improved the Ptolemaic system that it was mathematically equivalent to the Copernican system, although it was still geocentric. And yet the lead was lost in one area after another as the West surged ahead and Arabic science decayed.We may well pause and ask ourselves what would have been the consequences for world history if they, and not the medievals, had developed our modern scientific knowledge of the world. It was one of the most monumental failures of history. They had a start of five hundred years, and a great Empire stretching from Cordoba to Baghdad. What was missing? It is simply that Islamic theology emphasises the freedom of Allah at the expense of His rationality, so that their grasp of the order of the world is not strong enough for science to develop.
It is also part of Muslim belief that scientific research should not be undertaken unless it can be shown that it will lead to a useful practical result. This error appears again in Marxism. At first it sounds plausible enough, even praiseworthy. Scientific research is very expensive, so why should society pay for it if it is not going to produce anything useful?
This argument is based on a misunderstanding of the very nature of scientific research, which can only develop in accord with its own internal criteria. It cannot, except in a very general way, be directed by external criteria, however laudable they may be. Scientists want to find out about the world; this is their motive and should be their only reward. If Roentgen had been interested in helping medical diagnosis he would never have found X-rays. If Madame Curie had started by looking for a cure for cancer she would never have found radium. As in these examples, it often happens that after the scientist has found some new property of the world, it is found to have great practical value and can be used to benefit society. Scientists welcome this, but the prospect of such applications cannot be allowed to affect the conduct of their research.
The reason why modern science never developed in Muslim countries is thus a theological one. They need European science and technology, and are willing to pay for it. Unfortunately however, that very science is alien to them as it is based on Christian beliefs about the world that they cannot share. There are of course many eminent Muslim scientists, but most of them have been trained in Western countries and so have come to share implicitly those Christian beliefs about the world on which Science is based. There do not as yet seem to be many indications that science has really taken root in Muslim countries.
References
M. Clagett, The Science of Mechanics in the Middle Ages. Madison, 1959.A.C. Crombie, Augustine to Galileo, The History of Science 400-1650. Falcon, 1952.
A.C. Crombie, Robert Grosseteste and the Origins of Experimental Science 1100-1700. Oxford, 1953.
C. Dawson, Progress and Religion. Sheed and Ward, 1929.
C. Dawson, Religion and the Rise of Western Culture. Sheed and Ward, 1950.
E.Gilson, The Spirit of Medieval Philosophy. Sheed and Ward, 1936.
E. Gilson, The History of Christian Philosophy in the Middle Ages. Sheed and Ward, 1954.
J. Gimpel, The Medieval Machine. Pimlico, 1992.
E. Grant, Physical Science in the Middle Ages. Cambridge, 1977.
E. Grant, Planets, Stars and Orbs: The Medieval Cosmos 1200-1687. Cambridge, 1994.
F. Heer, The Medieval World. Wiedenfeld and Nicholson, 1961 (Ch. 12).
T.E. Huff, The Rise of Early Modern Science: Islam, China and the West. Cambridge, 1993.
S.L. Jaki, Science and Creation. Scottish Academic Press, 1986.
S.L. Jaki, Uneasy Genius: The Life and Work of Pierre Duhem. Martinus Nijhoff, 1984.
S.L. Jaki, "The Physics of Impetus and the Impetus of the Koran." "Science and Censorship: Helene Duhem and the Publication of the Systeme du Monde." Chapters 9 and 11 in The Absolute Beneath the Relative. University Press of America, 1988.
S.L. Jaki, Reluctant Heroine: The Life and Work of Helene Duhem. Scottish Academic Press, 1992.
S.L. Jaki, "Medieval Christianity: Its Inventiveness in Technology and Science." Article in: Technology in the Western Political Tradition. Ed. M.R. Zinman. Cornell U. Press,1993.
D.C. Lindberg (Ed), Science in the Middle Ages, Chicago, 1978.
J.A. Weisheipl. The Development of Physical Theory in the Middle Ages. Sheed & Ward,1959.
A.N. Whitehead, Science and the Modern World. Cambridge, 1926.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)